紀念偉大的哲學家愛德曼·胡塞爾
作者:捨斯托夫
文章來源:中國現象學網
瀏覽:281 次
In memory of a great philosopher Edmund Husserl
[俄]捨斯托夫
1
Max Scheler, when I last saw him, two weeks before his death, suddenly asked me: "Warum sind Sie mit so einem Ungest?m gegen Husserl losgegangen?" Husserl himself, when I visited him in Freiburg, introduced me to a group of visiting American professors of philosophy with the words: "No one has ever attacked me so sharply as he - and that's why we are such close friends." What astonishes one in Husserl's words is the clear expression of the "disinterestedness" which is so rare even in the great philosophers. His first interest was in the truth: and in the search for truth friendship with one's intellectual opponents is not only possible but essential. This is characteristic of Husserl in the highest degree.
But we are concerned for the moment with a different question: What could have been the cause of my harsh attack? To make intelligible a position as difficult and at the same time remarkable as Husserl's phenomenology, it seems to me useful to state not only the doctrine itself but also the reasons why I have found it, and still find it, unacceptable. Objections illuminate not only the views of the critic, but also those of the thinker criticized.[1]
I first encountered Husserl's works thirty years ago,[2] at a time when he had published only the Logische Untersuchungen. That book was and is enormously impressive. Among philosophers of the early twentieth century few indeed can rival Husserl in power, boldness, depth, and significance of thought. We did not meet until much later, after I had published two articles on Husserl in the Revue Philosophique.[3] I had been invited to Amsterdam to read a paper before a philosophical society. When I got there I was told that Husserl was coming later to read a paper and that he had asked if I could await his arrival so that we might meet. Of course, I gladly postponed my departure for a few days. I was pleasantly surprised by Husserl's desire to meet an outspoken intellectual opponent: such generosity of spirit is extremely rare.
Our first meeting took place at the philosophical society in the evening just before Husserl was to read his paper. At that time, of course, there was no philosophic discussion. Husserl was busy completing his own paper, which lasted for more than two hours and which, incidentally, he read standing, with extraordinary ease, and with the artistry and vigor of a man of forty rather than seventy. Husserl asked the member of the philosophic society in whose home he and his wife were staying (it is the custom in Amsterdam for philosophers who are invited to read papers to stay with members of the philosophic society rather than in hotels) to invite me for dinner the following day. At dinner, of course, there was no talk of philosophy. But immediately after dinner, as soon as we had gone from the dining room into the study, Husserl began to raise philosophic issues, plunging directly in medias res. This was characteristic of him. I remember that when, a few days later, both of us had dinner with another member of the society, and after dinner our host, a very wealthy man and a passionate bibliophile, began showing Husserl some of his rare books - first editions of the Critique of Pure Reason and Spinoza's Ethics - Husserl, to the great chagrin of our host, cast only a perfunctory glance at these rare volumes, and in a few moments took me aside and began to talk philosophy.
This same concentration upon the questions which absorbed him was apparent on another occasion, when, at the request of Professor Andler, I began to sound Husserl out concerning his willingness to come to Paris at the invitation of the Sorbonne. He asked me only one question: "Do you think that I will find people in Paris who know German and are willing to reflect upon my problems?" Husserl's complete absorption in philosophy was evident in all of our conversations - first in Amsterdam, and then in Freiburg and Paris. "You were wrong," he began at our first meeting, throwing himself upon me sharply and passionately,
"You have turned me into a stone statue, raised me onto a lofty pedestal, and then with hammer blows you have shattered this statue to bits. But am I really so lapidary? You don't seem to have noticed what compelled me to formulate in such a radical way the question of the nature of knowledge, modifying the dominant theories of knowledge which previously had satisfied me as much as any other philosopher. The more deeply I probed into the basic problems of logic, the more I felt that our science, our knowledge, is shaking, tottering. And finally, to my own indescribable horror, I convinced myself that if contemporary philosophy has said the last word about the nature of knowledge, then we have no knowledge. Once, when I was giving a lecture at the university, expounding ideas which I had taken over from our contemporaries, I suddenly felt that I had nothing to say, that I was standing before my students with empty hands and an empty soul. And then I resolved both for myself and for my students to submit the existing theories of knowledge to that severe and unrelenting criticism which has aroused the indignation of so many people. On the other hand, I began to seek the truth precisely where no one had sought it before, since no one had admitted that it might be found there. Such was the origin of my Logical Investigations. But you did not want to see in my struggle, in my impetuous "either-or," an expression of what it in fact was - namely, the consciousness that, if the doubts which had arisen in me could not be overcome by the efforts of reason, if we are doomed merely to go on smoothing over - more or less thoroughly - the fissures and crevasses which have opened up in all of our epistemological constructions, then one fine day all of our knowledge will crumble and we will find ourselves standing amid the miserable ruins of former greatness."
It was in roughly these words, but with greater force and passion, with that extraordinary ?lan which one felt in all of his remarkable writings and addresses, that Husserl spoke to me of the sources of his bold and original philosophy, a philosophy which relentlessly swept away the fundamental ideas of the best contemporary thinkers. The Logische Untersuchungen and his other works were a "slaughter," not of the "innocent," of course, (the innocent do not philosophize), but of the old men. At the same time they were a grandiose and magnificent attempt to find a support for our knowledge, a support which even the "gates of Hell" could not vanquish. Husserl spoke with sincerity, enthusiasm, and inspiration; I think even non-philosophers would immediately sense that the questions he raised were not theoretical ones - any proffered solution to which, being equally indifferent, would be equally acceptable - but questions, as he himself put it, of life and death. Husserl, like Shakespeare's Hamlet, raised the terrible and fateful question, "to be or not to be." He saw with Hamlet (or with Shakespeare) that the time was out of joint. His words had a truly shattering impact. My first personal meetings with him, like my reading of his first words twenty years earlier, was truly memorable. One does not forget such human greatness.
I replied candidly - "You are right, of course. I have attacked your ideas with all the energy I could command. But this was only because I felt the enormous and incomparable power of your thought, and sensed what you have now told me about the motivations of your bold and original ideas. I have no doubt that in France - where you were almost entirely unknown before my articles appeared - people now realize that a neighboring country has produced a major philosopher who has opened up horizons hitherto obscured by the thick haze of traditional commonplaces. The sharpness of my attack emphasizes, rather than deprecates, the enormous significance of what you have done for philosophy. To struggle with you one must marshal all of his spiritual energies; every intense effort presupposes passion and the sharpness of passion. I was faced by a fearful dilemma: either to accept your whole position and its as-yet-unformulated philosophical implications - or to rebel against you. And if in the next world I am accused of betraying philosophy because of my struggle against self-evidence [4]. I shall point to you, and you will burn in my place. You have pursued and persecuted me so persistently and inexorably with your intuitive self-evidence, that I could find no other way out. Either I had to submit to you in everything, or else steel myself for the desperate step of revolt, not only against you but against everything that has always been considered the unquestioned foundation of philosophy and of thought. I had to revolt against self-evident truth. You were profoundly right when you said that the time was out of joint. Every attempt to examine the least fissure in the foundation of human knowledge throws the time out of joint. But must knowledge be preserved at whatever cost? Must the time be put back in joint? Or rather, should we not give it a further push - and shatter it to bits?"
This conversation - here given in brief and approximate outline - brought to a focus what united, and also what divided, us. Strange as it may seem to some people, my first teacher of philosophy was Shakespeare, with his enigmatic, incomprehensible, threatening, and melancholy words: "the time is out of joint." What can one do, how can one act, when the time is out of joint, when being reveals its horrors?" From Shakespeare I turned eagerly to Kant, who, with the incomparable artistry of his Critique of Practical Reason, by means of his famous postulates, attempted to gloss over, and for centuries succeeded in glossing over, the ontological fissures laid bare by his own critique of pure reason. But Kant had no answer for my questions. I next turned to a different source - the Scriptures. But surely the Scriptures cannot bear comparison with self-evidence? At that time I had not yet come to the point of asking this question. Even those who acknowledge papal infallibility have not come to the point of raising it. Men content themselves with the postulates of practical reason, using them to soften, - or rather to forget, or fail to see - the all-destroying power of the truths of theoretical reason.
Almost all of my conversations with Husserl revolved about these themes. When he visited me at my home in Paris, immediately after dinner (which he seemed not even to have noticed), he took me into another room and immediately plunged into philosophical discussion. At that time I was working on the first part of my book Athens and Jerusalem, - the section called "Parmenides in Chains". Naturally, I tried to direct our discussion toward the topics which I was then treating. I said to Husserl, using almost the same words that I later used in "Parmenides in Chains": In 399 B.C. Socrates was poisoned. Socrates left behind his disciple Plato, who, "forced by the truth itself' (in Aristotle's expression), did not, could not refrain from thinking and saying that Socrates had been poisoned. All of his writings elaborate a single central question: Is there any power in the world which can reconcile us to the fact that Socrates was poisoned? For Aristotle such a question would have been nonsensical. He was convinced that the "truth," "a dog was poisoned," like the "truth," "Socrates was poisoned," is permanently immune from human or divine objection. The hemlock makes no distinction between Socrates and dogs. Similarly, forced by the truth itself, we are obliged to make no distinction between Socrates and dogs, even mad dogs.
I expected Husserl to greet these remarks with a burst of indignation. But something else happened: He listened intently as though, in the depths of his being, he had already long since recognized that the Aristotelian "forced by truth itself' contained a kind of falsehood or betrayal. I was the more astonished in that we had previously disputed warmly as to what philosophy is. I had said that philosophy is a great and ultimate struggle; he had answered sharply, Nein, Philosophie ist Besinnung. But now our conversation took a different turn. It was as though he felt the Aristotelian certitude to be built upon sand. In any case, Husserl arranged to have my "Parmenides in Chains" published as an article in the journal Logos, for which it was wholly unsuited both because of its length, and more importantly, because it challenged the conviction that men can never free themselves from such truths as "Socrates was poisoned." Husserl's mind, I repeat, was open to everything. Soon after my article had appeared he wrote me: "Your ways are not my ways, but I understand and value your problems."[5] I then understood the strange fact that during my visit to Freiburg, learning that I had never read Kierkegaard, Husserl began not to ask but to demand - with enigmatic insistence - that I acquaint myself with the works of the Danish thinker. How was it that a man whose whole life had been a celebration of reason should have led me to Kierkegaard's hymn to the absurd? Husserl, to be sure, seems to have become acquainted with Kierkegaard only during the last years of his life. There is no evidence in his works of familiarity with any of the writings of the author of Either-Or. But it seems clear that Kierkegaard's ideas deeply impressed him.
2
On one view the aim of Husserl's phenomenology is purely methodological; such a view is profoundly mistaken and serves merely to veil the breadth and significance of Husserl's complex of problems. He himself writes: "Philosophy... is a science of the true principles, the sources, the "rhidz?mata pant?n."(Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft," Logos 1 (1910-11), p. 340) Such a definition makes his aim clear enough. His long article, "Philosophy as an Exact Science," written with extraordinary ?lan, represents not the results but a kind of manifesto of the phenomenological school, a concise statement of the position which he had developed and was to develop further in his major works, Logische Untersuchungen [1900,1901] and Ideen zu einer reinen Ph?nomenologie... [1913]. With the audacity of a man destined to do great things, Husserl declares:
In the whole life of the modern period there is perhaps no idea more powerful, more irresistible in its advance, than the idea of science. Nothing will block its triumphant course. In the pursuit of its legitimate goals it is indeed all-encompassing. Conceived in its ideal perfection, it would be reason itself, admitting no other authority beside it or above it... Science has spoken, from now on wisdom must learn from it.(Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft," Logos 1 (1910-11), p. 296, 334)
Husserl's forceful statement is reminiscent of the well-known saying, Roma locuta, causa finita.
However, we should not assume that Husserl repudiated the whole of earlier philosophy. On the contrary, he had a lively sense of his own continuity with the great thinkers of the past:
A fully-conscious will toward exact science rules the Socratic-Platonic revolution in philosophy and also the scientific reactions against scholasticism of the early modern period, in particular the Cartesian revolution. Their impulse carried over to the great philosophies of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, was reviewed with the most radical energy in Kant's Vernunftkritik, and continued to exert controlling influence upon the philosophy of Fichte.(Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft," Logos 1 (1910-11), p. 292)
It was only contemporary philosophy that Husserl condemned unconditionally, and here his attack was merciless:
It lacks even the beginning of a scientifically rigorous doctrine,... it is at most a scientific semifinished product, or an undifferentiated mixture of Weltanschauung and theoretical knowledge.(Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft," Logos 1 (1910-11), p. 335)
What Husserl calls Weltanschauung (or Weisheit) arouses his deepest indignation:
...we must remember our responsibility to mankind. We must not sacrifice eternity to time; we must not, in order to meet our own need, bequeath new needs to our posterity as an ultimately ineradicable evil... Weltanschauungen clash; only science is decisive, and its decisions bear the stamp of eternity. (Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft," Logos 1 (1910-11), p. 337)
These challenging words are directed against the philosophy of the second half of the nineteenth century: Mill, Bain, Wundt, Sigwart, Erdmann, Lipps, Dilthey. He accuses them all of "psychologism," that is, relativism. Even the ancients had revealed the internal contradiction of relativism. Relativism, Aristotle declared - and not as a truth which he himself had discovered, but as a generally known truth - is self-destructive. For Husserl this proposition is the starting point for all of his investigations. Of course, his opponents reject Protagoras' thesis that "man is the measure of all things." But Husserl shows that, unconsciously or covertly, they are wholly in the power of Protagoras' idea; they fail to realize this only because they are not absolute relativists but what he calls "specific" [or "species"] relativists.(Logische Untersuchungen, 1:116 ff.) They see the senselessness of the assertion that every man can have his own truth, but they do not see the equal senselessness of the assertion that man as a species has his own truth. In opposition to all such contemporary philosophers, Husserl declares with magnificent passion:
What is true is absolutely true, is true "in itself." Truth is identically one, whether it be apprehended in the judgments of men or of monsters [Menschen oder Unmenschen], of angels or of gods.(Logische Untersuchungen, 1:117 ff.)
All of Husserl is in these words, the whole enormous, almost superhuman task which he set himself and philosophy - the search for the principles, sources, and roots of all that is. After Kant - and especially after his Critique of Pure Reason - such a claim seems utterly fantastic. Who is willing to speak seriously of such a thing as absolute truth? Husserl, of course, knows very well that contemporary thought is afraid of approaching within cannon range of such a judgment. All epistemologists speak of self-evident truths, but for them self-evidence, our certainty of the existence of universal and necessary judgments is only, in Sigwart's expression, "a postulate beyond which we cannot go," a certainty which is maintained only by subjective consciousness, "the feeling of certainty which accompanies a certain portion of our thought." This was the position of such an outstanding thinker as Erdmann. These thinkers seemed to want to assume that the feeling of self-evidence was a "sufficient reason" which would justify our confidence in the results of scientific investigation. But Husserl saw in such frivolous assumptions, whether conscious or unconscious, a fatal danger to philosophy. In answer to Erdmann and Sigwart he wrote:
[On such a view] there might be creatures of a special kind, logical supermen [Ubermenschen] so to speak, for whom not our fundamental principles, but quite different ones, would be valid; what is truth for us would be falsity for them. It may be true for them that they do not experience the psychic phenomena which they in fact experience. It may be true for us that we and they exist, but it may be false for them, etc. Of course, we ordinary logical creatures [Logische Alltagsmenschen] would judge such creatures to be out of their senses: they speak of truth and at the same time destroy its laws; they claim to have their own laws of thought, and yet they deny the laws upon which the possibility of law in general rests.. .In their thinking "yes" and "no," truth and error, being and non-being, would lose all distinctness. (Logische Untersuchungen, 1:151 ff.)
Husserl, of course, does not limit himself to such solemn pronouncements. The threat of the madhouse which is implicit in the words just quoted goes far beyond the limits of a simple pronoun Cement. The senselessness which is exhibited by the assertions of relativism - whether individual or "specific" - cannot fail to arouse the anxiety of the conscientious investigator.
In the second volume of his Logische Untersuchungen Husserl formulates the same idea in a calmer but no less powerful way: "We shall never admit that anything which is logically or geometrically absurd can be psychologically possible." We admit, he explains, that "logical concepts have a psychological origin, but we reject the conclusion which is drawn from this fact." What conclusion? And why do we reject it? - "For our discipli
作者:捨斯托夫
文章來源:中國現象學網
瀏覽:281 次
In memory of a great philosopher Edmund Husserl
[俄]捨斯托夫
1
Max Scheler, when I last saw him, two weeks before his death, suddenly asked me: "Warum sind Sie mit so einem Ungest?m gegen Husserl losgegangen?" Husserl himself, when I visited him in Freiburg, introduced me to a group of visiting American professors of philosophy with the words: "No one has ever attacked me so sharply as he - and that's why we are such close friends." What astonishes one in Husserl's words is the clear expression of the "disinterestedness" which is so rare even in the great philosophers. His first interest was in the truth: and in the search for truth friendship with one's intellectual opponents is not only possible but essential. This is characteristic of Husserl in the highest degree.
But we are concerned for the moment with a different question: What could have been the cause of my harsh attack? To make intelligible a position as difficult and at the same time remarkable as Husserl's phenomenology, it seems to me useful to state not only the doctrine itself but also the reasons why I have found it, and still find it, unacceptable. Objections illuminate not only the views of the critic, but also those of the thinker criticized.[1]
I first encountered Husserl's works thirty years ago,[2] at a time when he had published only the Logische Untersuchungen. That book was and is enormously impressive. Among philosophers of the early twentieth century few indeed can rival Husserl in power, boldness, depth, and significance of thought. We did not meet until much later, after I had published two articles on Husserl in the Revue Philosophique.[3] I had been invited to Amsterdam to read a paper before a philosophical society. When I got there I was told that Husserl was coming later to read a paper and that he had asked if I could await his arrival so that we might meet. Of course, I gladly postponed my departure for a few days. I was pleasantly surprised by Husserl's desire to meet an outspoken intellectual opponent: such generosity of spirit is extremely rare.
Our first meeting took place at the philosophical society in the evening just before Husserl was to read his paper. At that time, of course, there was no philosophic discussion. Husserl was busy completing his own paper, which lasted for more than two hours and which, incidentally, he read standing, with extraordinary ease, and with the artistry and vigor of a man of forty rather than seventy. Husserl asked the member of the philosophic society in whose home he and his wife were staying (it is the custom in Amsterdam for philosophers who are invited to read papers to stay with members of the philosophic society rather than in hotels) to invite me for dinner the following day. At dinner, of course, there was no talk of philosophy. But immediately after dinner, as soon as we had gone from the dining room into the study, Husserl began to raise philosophic issues, plunging directly in medias res. This was characteristic of him. I remember that when, a few days later, both of us had dinner with another member of the society, and after dinner our host, a very wealthy man and a passionate bibliophile, began showing Husserl some of his rare books - first editions of the Critique of Pure Reason and Spinoza's Ethics - Husserl, to the great chagrin of our host, cast only a perfunctory glance at these rare volumes, and in a few moments took me aside and began to talk philosophy.
This same concentration upon the questions which absorbed him was apparent on another occasion, when, at the request of Professor Andler, I began to sound Husserl out concerning his willingness to come to Paris at the invitation of the Sorbonne. He asked me only one question: "Do you think that I will find people in Paris who know German and are willing to reflect upon my problems?" Husserl's complete absorption in philosophy was evident in all of our conversations - first in Amsterdam, and then in Freiburg and Paris. "You were wrong," he began at our first meeting, throwing himself upon me sharply and passionately,
"You have turned me into a stone statue, raised me onto a lofty pedestal, and then with hammer blows you have shattered this statue to bits. But am I really so lapidary? You don't seem to have noticed what compelled me to formulate in such a radical way the question of the nature of knowledge, modifying the dominant theories of knowledge which previously had satisfied me as much as any other philosopher. The more deeply I probed into the basic problems of logic, the more I felt that our science, our knowledge, is shaking, tottering. And finally, to my own indescribable horror, I convinced myself that if contemporary philosophy has said the last word about the nature of knowledge, then we have no knowledge. Once, when I was giving a lecture at the university, expounding ideas which I had taken over from our contemporaries, I suddenly felt that I had nothing to say, that I was standing before my students with empty hands and an empty soul. And then I resolved both for myself and for my students to submit the existing theories of knowledge to that severe and unrelenting criticism which has aroused the indignation of so many people. On the other hand, I began to seek the truth precisely where no one had sought it before, since no one had admitted that it might be found there. Such was the origin of my Logical Investigations. But you did not want to see in my struggle, in my impetuous "either-or," an expression of what it in fact was - namely, the consciousness that, if the doubts which had arisen in me could not be overcome by the efforts of reason, if we are doomed merely to go on smoothing over - more or less thoroughly - the fissures and crevasses which have opened up in all of our epistemological constructions, then one fine day all of our knowledge will crumble and we will find ourselves standing amid the miserable ruins of former greatness."
It was in roughly these words, but with greater force and passion, with that extraordinary ?lan which one felt in all of his remarkable writings and addresses, that Husserl spoke to me of the sources of his bold and original philosophy, a philosophy which relentlessly swept away the fundamental ideas of the best contemporary thinkers. The Logische Untersuchungen and his other works were a "slaughter," not of the "innocent," of course, (the innocent do not philosophize), but of the old men. At the same time they were a grandiose and magnificent attempt to find a support for our knowledge, a support which even the "gates of Hell" could not vanquish. Husserl spoke with sincerity, enthusiasm, and inspiration; I think even non-philosophers would immediately sense that the questions he raised were not theoretical ones - any proffered solution to which, being equally indifferent, would be equally acceptable - but questions, as he himself put it, of life and death. Husserl, like Shakespeare's Hamlet, raised the terrible and fateful question, "to be or not to be." He saw with Hamlet (or with Shakespeare) that the time was out of joint. His words had a truly shattering impact. My first personal meetings with him, like my reading of his first words twenty years earlier, was truly memorable. One does not forget such human greatness.
I replied candidly - "You are right, of course. I have attacked your ideas with all the energy I could command. But this was only because I felt the enormous and incomparable power of your thought, and sensed what you have now told me about the motivations of your bold and original ideas. I have no doubt that in France - where you were almost entirely unknown before my articles appeared - people now realize that a neighboring country has produced a major philosopher who has opened up horizons hitherto obscured by the thick haze of traditional commonplaces. The sharpness of my attack emphasizes, rather than deprecates, the enormous significance of what you have done for philosophy. To struggle with you one must marshal all of his spiritual energies; every intense effort presupposes passion and the sharpness of passion. I was faced by a fearful dilemma: either to accept your whole position and its as-yet-unformulated philosophical implications - or to rebel against you. And if in the next world I am accused of betraying philosophy because of my struggle against self-evidence [4]. I shall point to you, and you will burn in my place. You have pursued and persecuted me so persistently and inexorably with your intuitive self-evidence, that I could find no other way out. Either I had to submit to you in everything, or else steel myself for the desperate step of revolt, not only against you but against everything that has always been considered the unquestioned foundation of philosophy and of thought. I had to revolt against self-evident truth. You were profoundly right when you said that the time was out of joint. Every attempt to examine the least fissure in the foundation of human knowledge throws the time out of joint. But must knowledge be preserved at whatever cost? Must the time be put back in joint? Or rather, should we not give it a further push - and shatter it to bits?"
This conversation - here given in brief and approximate outline - brought to a focus what united, and also what divided, us. Strange as it may seem to some people, my first teacher of philosophy was Shakespeare, with his enigmatic, incomprehensible, threatening, and melancholy words: "the time is out of joint." What can one do, how can one act, when the time is out of joint, when being reveals its horrors?" From Shakespeare I turned eagerly to Kant, who, with the incomparable artistry of his Critique of Practical Reason, by means of his famous postulates, attempted to gloss over, and for centuries succeeded in glossing over, the ontological fissures laid bare by his own critique of pure reason. But Kant had no answer for my questions. I next turned to a different source - the Scriptures. But surely the Scriptures cannot bear comparison with self-evidence? At that time I had not yet come to the point of asking this question. Even those who acknowledge papal infallibility have not come to the point of raising it. Men content themselves with the postulates of practical reason, using them to soften, - or rather to forget, or fail to see - the all-destroying power of the truths of theoretical reason.
Almost all of my conversations with Husserl revolved about these themes. When he visited me at my home in Paris, immediately after dinner (which he seemed not even to have noticed), he took me into another room and immediately plunged into philosophical discussion. At that time I was working on the first part of my book Athens and Jerusalem, - the section called "Parmenides in Chains". Naturally, I tried to direct our discussion toward the topics which I was then treating. I said to Husserl, using almost the same words that I later used in "Parmenides in Chains": In 399 B.C. Socrates was poisoned. Socrates left behind his disciple Plato, who, "forced by the truth itself' (in Aristotle's expression), did not, could not refrain from thinking and saying that Socrates had been poisoned. All of his writings elaborate a single central question: Is there any power in the world which can reconcile us to the fact that Socrates was poisoned? For Aristotle such a question would have been nonsensical. He was convinced that the "truth," "a dog was poisoned," like the "truth," "Socrates was poisoned," is permanently immune from human or divine objection. The hemlock makes no distinction between Socrates and dogs. Similarly, forced by the truth itself, we are obliged to make no distinction between Socrates and dogs, even mad dogs.
I expected Husserl to greet these remarks with a burst of indignation. But something else happened: He listened intently as though, in the depths of his being, he had already long since recognized that the Aristotelian "forced by truth itself' contained a kind of falsehood or betrayal. I was the more astonished in that we had previously disputed warmly as to what philosophy is. I had said that philosophy is a great and ultimate struggle; he had answered sharply, Nein, Philosophie ist Besinnung. But now our conversation took a different turn. It was as though he felt the Aristotelian certitude to be built upon sand. In any case, Husserl arranged to have my "Parmenides in Chains" published as an article in the journal Logos, for which it was wholly unsuited both because of its length, and more importantly, because it challenged the conviction that men can never free themselves from such truths as "Socrates was poisoned." Husserl's mind, I repeat, was open to everything. Soon after my article had appeared he wrote me: "Your ways are not my ways, but I understand and value your problems."[5] I then understood the strange fact that during my visit to Freiburg, learning that I had never read Kierkegaard, Husserl began not to ask but to demand - with enigmatic insistence - that I acquaint myself with the works of the Danish thinker. How was it that a man whose whole life had been a celebration of reason should have led me to Kierkegaard's hymn to the absurd? Husserl, to be sure, seems to have become acquainted with Kierkegaard only during the last years of his life. There is no evidence in his works of familiarity with any of the writings of the author of Either-Or. But it seems clear that Kierkegaard's ideas deeply impressed him.
2
On one view the aim of Husserl's phenomenology is purely methodological; such a view is profoundly mistaken and serves merely to veil the breadth and significance of Husserl's complex of problems. He himself writes: "Philosophy... is a science of the true principles, the sources, the "rhidz?mata pant?n."(Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft," Logos 1 (1910-11), p. 340) Such a definition makes his aim clear enough. His long article, "Philosophy as an Exact Science," written with extraordinary ?lan, represents not the results but a kind of manifesto of the phenomenological school, a concise statement of the position which he had developed and was to develop further in his major works, Logische Untersuchungen [1900,1901] and Ideen zu einer reinen Ph?nomenologie... [1913]. With the audacity of a man destined to do great things, Husserl declares:
In the whole life of the modern period there is perhaps no idea more powerful, more irresistible in its advance, than the idea of science. Nothing will block its triumphant course. In the pursuit of its legitimate goals it is indeed all-encompassing. Conceived in its ideal perfection, it would be reason itself, admitting no other authority beside it or above it... Science has spoken, from now on wisdom must learn from it.(Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft," Logos 1 (1910-11), p. 296, 334)
Husserl's forceful statement is reminiscent of the well-known saying, Roma locuta, causa finita.
However, we should not assume that Husserl repudiated the whole of earlier philosophy. On the contrary, he had a lively sense of his own continuity with the great thinkers of the past:
A fully-conscious will toward exact science rules the Socratic-Platonic revolution in philosophy and also the scientific reactions against scholasticism of the early modern period, in particular the Cartesian revolution. Their impulse carried over to the great philosophies of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, was reviewed with the most radical energy in Kant's Vernunftkritik, and continued to exert controlling influence upon the philosophy of Fichte.(Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft," Logos 1 (1910-11), p. 292)
It was only contemporary philosophy that Husserl condemned unconditionally, and here his attack was merciless:
It lacks even the beginning of a scientifically rigorous doctrine,... it is at most a scientific semifinished product, or an undifferentiated mixture of Weltanschauung and theoretical knowledge.(Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft," Logos 1 (1910-11), p. 335)
What Husserl calls Weltanschauung (or Weisheit) arouses his deepest indignation:
...we must remember our responsibility to mankind. We must not sacrifice eternity to time; we must not, in order to meet our own need, bequeath new needs to our posterity as an ultimately ineradicable evil... Weltanschauungen clash; only science is decisive, and its decisions bear the stamp of eternity. (Philosophie als strenge Wissenschaft," Logos 1 (1910-11), p. 337)
These challenging words are directed against the philosophy of the second half of the nineteenth century: Mill, Bain, Wundt, Sigwart, Erdmann, Lipps, Dilthey. He accuses them all of "psychologism," that is, relativism. Even the ancients had revealed the internal contradiction of relativism. Relativism, Aristotle declared - and not as a truth which he himself had discovered, but as a generally known truth - is self-destructive. For Husserl this proposition is the starting point for all of his investigations. Of course, his opponents reject Protagoras' thesis that "man is the measure of all things." But Husserl shows that, unconsciously or covertly, they are wholly in the power of Protagoras' idea; they fail to realize this only because they are not absolute relativists but what he calls "specific" [or "species"] relativists.(Logische Untersuchungen, 1:116 ff.) They see the senselessness of the assertion that every man can have his own truth, but they do not see the equal senselessness of the assertion that man as a species has his own truth. In opposition to all such contemporary philosophers, Husserl declares with magnificent passion:
What is true is absolutely true, is true "in itself." Truth is identically one, whether it be apprehended in the judgments of men or of monsters [Menschen oder Unmenschen], of angels or of gods.(Logische Untersuchungen, 1:117 ff.)
All of Husserl is in these words, the whole enormous, almost superhuman task which he set himself and philosophy - the search for the principles, sources, and roots of all that is. After Kant - and especially after his Critique of Pure Reason - such a claim seems utterly fantastic. Who is willing to speak seriously of such a thing as absolute truth? Husserl, of course, knows very well that contemporary thought is afraid of approaching within cannon range of such a judgment. All epistemologists speak of self-evident truths, but for them self-evidence, our certainty of the existence of universal and necessary judgments is only, in Sigwart's expression, "a postulate beyond which we cannot go," a certainty which is maintained only by subjective consciousness, "the feeling of certainty which accompanies a certain portion of our thought." This was the position of such an outstanding thinker as Erdmann. These thinkers seemed to want to assume that the feeling of self-evidence was a "sufficient reason" which would justify our confidence in the results of scientific investigation. But Husserl saw in such frivolous assumptions, whether conscious or unconscious, a fatal danger to philosophy. In answer to Erdmann and Sigwart he wrote:
[On such a view] there might be creatures of a special kind, logical supermen [Ubermenschen] so to speak, for whom not our fundamental principles, but quite different ones, would be valid; what is truth for us would be falsity for them. It may be true for them that they do not experience the psychic phenomena which they in fact experience. It may be true for us that we and they exist, but it may be false for them, etc. Of course, we ordinary logical creatures [Logische Alltagsmenschen] would judge such creatures to be out of their senses: they speak of truth and at the same time destroy its laws; they claim to have their own laws of thought, and yet they deny the laws upon which the possibility of law in general rests.. .In their thinking "yes" and "no," truth and error, being and non-being, would lose all distinctness. (Logische Untersuchungen, 1:151 ff.)
Husserl, of course, does not limit himself to such solemn pronouncements. The threat of the madhouse which is implicit in the words just quoted goes far beyond the limits of a simple pronoun Cement. The senselessness which is exhibited by the assertions of relativism - whether individual or "specific" - cannot fail to arouse the anxiety of the conscientious investigator.
In the second volume of his Logische Untersuchungen Husserl formulates the same idea in a calmer but no less powerful way: "We shall never admit that anything which is logically or geometrically absurd can be psychologically possible." We admit, he explains, that "logical concepts have a psychological origin, but we reject the conclusion which is drawn from this fact." What conclusion? And why do we reject it? - "For our discipli
全站熱搜
留言列表